Adams, F., Aizawa, K. (2017). Causal theories of mental content, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Summer 2017 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/content-causal/>.
Anderson, M. (2003). Embodied cognition: a field guide. Artificial Intelligence. 149, 91–130.
Anderson, M. (2010). Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33, 245–266.
Arbib, M. (1987). Brains, machines, and mathematics, 2nd ed. Springer.
Barsalou, L. (2010). Grounded cognition: past, present, and future. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2, 716-724.
Barsalou, L. (2016a). On Staying Grounded and Avoiding Quixotic Dead Ends. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23, 1122–1142.
Barsalou, L. (2016b). Situated conceptualization: Theory and applications. In Foundations of embodied cognition: Volume 1 Perceptual and emotional embodiment (pp. 11-37). Psychology Press.
Barsalou, L. (2017). What does semantic tiling of the cortex tell us about semantics? Neuropsychologia, 105, 18-38.
Barsalou, L., Dutriaux, L., Scheepers, C. (2018). Moving beyond the distinction between concrete and abstract concepts. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 373.
Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 55, 7–19.
Binder J. (2016). In defense of abstract conceptual representations. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 23, 1096–1108.
Binder, J., Westbury, C., McKiernan, K., Possing, E., Medler, D. (2005). Distinct brain systems for processing concrete and abstract concepts. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 17, 905–917.
Binder,J., Desai,R., Graves,W., Conant, L. (2009). Where Is the semantic system? A critical review and meta-analysis of 120 functional neuroimaging studies. Cerebral Cortex, 19, 2767–2796.
Binder, J., Conant, L., Humphries, C., Fernandino, L., Simons, S., Aguilar, M., Desai, R. (2016). Toward a brain-based componential semantic representation. Cognitive Neuropsychology, 33, 130-174. DOI: 10.1080/02643294.2016.1147426
Boeckx, C., Grohmann, K. (Eds.) (2013). The Cambridge Handbook of biolinguistics. Cambridge University Press.
Boone, W., Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193, 1509-34.
Bradie, M., Harms, W. (2020). Evolutionary Epistemology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/epistemology-evolutionary/>.
Casey, M. (1996). The dynamics of discrete-time computation with application to recurrent neural networks and finite state machine extraction. Neural Computation, 8, 1135–1178.
Chomsky, N. (1956). Three models for the description of language. IRE Transactions on Information Theory, 2, 113–124.
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic Structures. Mouton.
Chomsky, N. (1959). On certain formal properties of grammars. Information and Control, 2, 137–167.
Chomsky, N. (1963). Formal properties of grammars. In R. D. Luce, R. R. Bush & E. Galanter (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology (pp. 323–418). John Wiley & Sons.
Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. (2000). The architecture of language, ed. N. Mukherji, B. Patnaik, R. Agnihotri. Oxford University Press.
Christiansen, M. (1992). The (non)necessity of recursion in natural language processing. Proceedings of the 14th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society. 665–670.
Christiansen, M., Chater, N. (1999). Towards a connectionist model of recursion in human linguistic performance. Cognitive Science, 23, 157-205.
Christiansen, M., Chater, N. (2008). Language as shaped by the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 31, 489-558.
Christiansen, M., MacDonald, M. (2009). A usage-based approach to recursion in sentence processing. Language Learning, 59, 126-161.
Churchland, P. (2012). Plato's camera. How the physical brain captures a landscape of abstract universals. MIT Press.
Cole, D. (2020). The Chinese Room Argument. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/chinese-room/>.
Conway C., Pisoni D. (2008). Neurocognitive basis of implicit learning of sequential structure and its relation to language processing. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1145, 113-31.
Dever, J. (2006). Compositionality. In E. Lepore & B. Smith (Eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (pp. 633-666). Oxford University Press.
De Vries, M., Monaghan, P., Knecht, S., Zwitserlood, P. (2008). Syntactic structure and artificial grammar learning: the learnability of embedded hierarchical structures. Cognition,107, 763–774.
De Vries, M., Christiansen, M., Petersson, K. (2011). Learning Recursion: Multiple Nested and Crossed Dependencies. Biolinguistics, 5, 10-35.
De Vries, M., Petersson, K., Geukes, S., Zwitserlood, P., Christiansen, M. (2012). Processing multiple non-adjacent dependencies: evidence from sequence learning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 2065-2076.
Downes, S. (2018). Evolutionary Psychology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/evolutionary-psychology/>.
Fernandino, L., Binder, J., Desai, R., Pendl, S., Humphries, C., Gross, W., Conant, L., Seidenberg, M. (2016). Concept Representation Reflects Multimodal Abstraction: A Framework for Embodied Semantics. Cerebral Cortex, 26, 2018–2034.
Fitch, W., Friederici, A. Hagoort, P. (2012). Pattern perception and computational complexity: introduction to the special issue. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 1925-1932.
Fitch, W., Friederici, A. (2012). Artificial grammar meets formal language theory: an overview. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 1933-1955.
Fodor J., Pylyshyn Z. (1988). Connectionism and cognitive architecture. Cognition, 28, 3–71.
Friederici, A. (2017). Language in our Brain: The origins of a uniquely human capacity. MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37, 1–22.
Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 227–242). Elsevier.
Gallistel, C. King, A. (2009). Memory and the computational brain: Why cognitive science will transform neuroscience. Wiley.
Gärdenfors, P. (2014) Geometry of meaning. Semantics based on conceptual spaces. MIT Press.
Garagnani, M., Pulvermüller, F. (2016). Conceptual grounding of language in action and perception: a neurocomputational model of the emergence of category specificity and semantic hubs, European Journal of Neuroscience, 43, 721-737.
Gazzaniga, M., Ivry, R., Mangun, G. (2019). Cognitive neuroscience: the biology of the mind. W. W. Norton.
Geeraerts, D., Cuyckens, H. (2012). Introducing cognitive linguistics. Oxford University Press.
Gładziejewski, P., & Miłkowski, M. (2017). Structural representations: Causally relevant and different from detectors. Biology and Philosophy, 32, 337–355.
Gold, E. (1967). Language Identification in the Limit. Information and Control, 10, 447–474.
Goodfellow, I., Bengio, Y. (2017). Deep Learning. MIT Press.
Haykin, S. (2008). Neural Networks: A Comprehensive Foundation. Prentice Hall.
Hochreiter, S., Schmidhuber, J. (1997). Long short-term memory. Neural Computation, 9, 1735-1780.
Hopcroft, J., Motwani, R., Ullman, J. (2000). Introduction to automata theory, languages, and computation. Reading. Addison-Wesley.
Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91, 683–704.
Jackendoff, R. (2002). Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. Oxford University Press.
Jackendoff, R. (2012). A User's Guide to Thought and Meaning. Oxford University Press.
Jacob, P. (2019). Intentionality. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Spring 2019 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/intentionality/>.
Jäger, G., Rogers, J. (2012). Formal language theory: refining the Chomsky hierarchy. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 1956–1970.
Johnson, K. (2004). Gold's theorem and cognitive science. Philosophy of Science, 70, 571–592.
Karlsson, F. (2007). Constraints on multiple initial embedding of clauses. International Journal of Corpus Linguistics, 12, 107-118.
Kemmerer, D. (2015). Cognitive Neuroscience of Language. Psychology Press.
Lange, S., Zeugmann, T., Zilles, S. (2008). Learning indexed families of recursive languages from positive data: a survey. Theoretical Computer Science, 397, 194-232.
Lau, J., Deutsch, M. (2014). Externalism About Mental Content. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/content-externalism/>.
Macleod, C. (2016). John Stuart Mill. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/mill/>.
Matheson, H., Barsalou, L. (2018). Embodiment and grounding in cognitive neuroscience. In J. Wixted, (Ed.) The Stevens’ Handbook of Experimental Psychology and Cognitive Neuroscience (4th ed.). Wiley.
McLaughlin, B., Bennett, K. (2018). Supervenience. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/supervenience/>.
Miller, G., Chomsky, N. (1963). Finitary models of language users. In D. Luce, R. Bush, E. Galanter, (Eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Psychology 2 (419-91). John Wiley & Sons.
Millikan R. (2004). Varieties of Meaning. MIT Press.
Moisl, H. (2020). Intrinsic Intentionality and Linguistic Meaning: An Historical Outline. In E. Kelih, R. Köhler (eds.) Words and Numbers. In Memory of Peter Grzybek 1957-2019 (148-166). RAM-Verlag.
Morgan, A., Piccinini, G. (2017). Towards a cognitive neuroscience of intentionality. Minds and Machines, 28, 119-139.
Neander, K. (2017). A mark of the mental: In defense of informational teleosemantics. MIT Press.
O'Connor, T. (2020). Emergent Properties. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, forthcoming URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/properties-emergent/>.
Oppy, G., Dowe, D. (2016). The Turing test. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/turing-test/>.
Papineau, D. (2020). Naturalism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/naturalism/>.
Patton, L. (2018). Hermann von Helmholtz. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2018/entries/hermann-helmholtz/>.
Petersson, K. (2005). On the relevance of the neurobiological analogue of the finite-state architecture. Neurocomputing, 65-66, 825-832.
Petersson, K., Grenholm, P., Forkstam, C. (2005). Artificial grammar learning and neural networks. Proceeding of the Cognitive Science Society, 2005, 1726–1731.
Petersson, K. , Folia, V., Hagoort, P. (2012). What artificial grammar learning reveals about the neurobiology of syntax. Brain and Language, 120, 83-95.
Petersson, K., Hagoort, P. (2012). The neurobiology of syntax: beyond string sets. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 367, 1971-1983.
Piccinini, G. (2009). Computationalism in the philosophy of mind. Philosophy Compass. 4, 515–532.
Piccinini, G. (2015). Physical computation. A mechanistic account. Oxford University Press.
Piccinini, G. (2016). The computational theory of cognition. In V. Müller (Ed.) Fundamental issues in artificial intelligence. Springer.
Piccinini, G. (2017). Computation in Physical Systems, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2017 Edition), ed. E. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/computation-physicalsystems/>.
Piccinini, G., Bahar, S. (2013). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive Science, 37, 453-488.
Piccinini, G., Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183, 283–311.
Piccinini, G., Scarantino, A. (2010). Computation vs. information processing: why their difference matters to cognitive science. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 237-246.
Piccinini, G., Scarantino, A. (2011). Information processing, computation, and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics, 37, 1-38.
Piccinini, G., Shagrir, O. (2014). Foundations of computational neuroscience. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 25, 25-30.
Plebe, A., de la Cruz, V. (2016). Neurosemantics. Neural processes and the construction of linguistic meaning. Springer.
Pojman, P. (2019). Ernst Mach. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/ernst-mach/>.
Pullum, G., Scholz, B. (2010). Recursion and the infinitude claim. In H. van der Hulst (Ed.), Recursion and Human Language (pp.111-138). De Gruyter Mouton.
Pulvermũller, F. (2012). Meaning and the brain: The neurosemantics of referential, interactive, and combinatorial knowledge. Journal of Neurolinguistics, 25, 423-459.
Pulvermũller, F. (2013). How neurons make meaning: brain mechanisms for embodied and abstract-symbolic semantics. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17, 458-70.
Ramsey, W. (2019). Eliminative Materialism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/materialism-eliminative/>.
Rescorla, M. (2009). Cognitive maps and the language of thought. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 377-407.
Rescorla, M. (2020). The computational theory of mind. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/computational-mind/>.
Rupert, R. (2008). Causal Theories of Mental Content. Philosophy Compass, 3, 353–380.
Ryder D. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: a theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19, 211–240.
Rysiew, P. (2020). Naturalism in Epistemology. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, forthcoming URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/epistemology-naturalized/>.
Scholz, B., Pelletier, F., Pullum, G. (2015). Philosophy of Linguistics. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (Winter 2016 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/linguistics/>.
Searle, J. (1980). Minds, Brains and Programs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 417–57.
Shagrir, O. (2018). The Brain as an input–output model of the world. Minds and Machines, 28, 53-75.
Shea, N. (2007). Consumers need information: Supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75, 404–435.
Shea, N. (2014). Exploitable isomorphism and structural representation. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 114, 123-144. .
Shea, N. (2018). Representation in cognitive science. Oxford University Press.
Siegelmann, H., Sontag, E. (1995). On the computational power of neural nets. Journal of Computer and System Sciences, 50, 132-50.
Siegelmann, H. (1999). Neural networks and analog computation: beyond the Turing limit. Birkhäuser.
Sipser, M. (2012). Introduction to the theory of computation, International edition. Thomson.
Smirnov, D. (2002) Homomorphism. In Encyclopedia of Mathematics. URL: http://encyclopediaofmath.org/index.php?title=Homomorphism&oldid=47265.
Speaks, J. (2021). Theories of meaning. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2021 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2021/entries/meaning/>.
Stoljar, D. (2015). Physicalism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/physicalism/>.
Szabó, Z. (2020). Compositionality. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/compositionality/>.
Tangirala, A. (2014). Principles of System Identification: Theory and Practice. CRC Press.
Thomson, E., Piccinini, G. (2018). Neural representations observed. Minds and Machines, 28, 191-235.
Tomasello, R., Garagnani, M., Wennekers, T., Pulvermüller, F. (2017). Brain connections of words, perceptions and actions: A neurobiological model of spatio-temporal semantic activation in the human cortex. Neuropsychologia, 98, 111-129.
van Riel, R., van Gulick, R. (2019). Scientific Reduction. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/scientific-reduction/>.
Wilson, R., Foglia, L. (2015). Embodied Cognition. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), ed. E. Zalta, URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/embodied-cognition/>.